One of my best commenters, William Westmiller, has kindly consented to provide a chapter-by-chapter critique of "The Scientific Worldview" (TSW). In addition to helping me with future work, I believe this will be valuable for new readers confronting deterministic assumptions and scientific interpretations for the first time. It might even be considered a sort of study guide for solitary readers of the book (just search the blog for "cotsw" to get the complete guide). You may remember Bill as the person who was “95% in agreement” with "The Ten Assumptions of Science" (TTAOS). His disagreement seems to stem from his belief in free will and the existence of finite particles, which is a critical part of a book he is writing on physics. I suspect that many folks new to univironmental determinism might have similar beliefs and that they would be interested in what Bill has to say. I will be forever grateful to Bill for all his work!
Bill’s critique from a semi-indeterministic point of view gives me a
chance to clarify points not well made previously. Do not expect me to give up
determinism or any of the Ten Assumptions because of any criticism. That would
be like expecting a regressive physicist to give up aether denial, more than
three dimensions, or the universe exploding out of nothing. As always, the
purpose of TTAOS is to provide a foundation for further work. Mostly, I shall try
to avoid debates about the appropriateness of those assumptions. I presented my
analysis of fundamental assumptions in the 2004 book and reiterated it in
Chapter 3 of TSW. We now can progress beyond that. The debates, of course, will
continue after the next indeterminist is born and begins to question how the
world really works.
Here is Bill’s first reservation with my response in brackets:
I've read everything (I think) that you've posted on
the web, but I hadn't found the time to read "The
Scientific Worldview" from beginning to end. After the first few
chapters, some reservations:
1. I was a little disappointed that you gave Marx
and Engels such prominent attention. They were primarily engaged in the
analysis of historic, social, economic, and political *extrapolations* of the
philosophy of "dialectical materialism". Marx never used the phrase
and Engels focused primarily on materialism.
I think this distracts from your review of the
philosophical foundations of science, which was a very peripheral issue to Marx
and Engels. I think it might have been better to extract elements of philosophy
and point to their originators (Aristotle, Plato, Socrates, and even Spinoza),
rather than adopting Marx as the primary guide for your ideas.
[One certainly could do as you suggest. This might have kept me out of
trouble with the mainstream. Unfortunately, those who tried that have failed.
Formal philosophy of science has been no threat to the current regressive
physics. But remember that I started this whole exploration because I could not
understand why otherwise smart folks believed in more than three dimensions and
the universe exploding from nothing. Collingwood and Kuhn hinted that the key
was to discover the assumptions lurking behind the whole train of thought
resulting in such weird conclusions. I could not readily find these assumptions
clearly stated in either the scientific or philosophy of science literature. So
I had to reach out in a big way.
Philosophy is the grandest achievement of humankind. When it is done properly, it should be the zusammenfassung (German for “together fastening”) of all knowledge. As a scientist, I have always believed in determinism: the proposition that “there are material causes for all effects.” So I took a cursory look at all philosophy with that in mind. What I found was a struggle of ideas between those who tended to believe in determinism and those who did not. Throughout history philosophy vacillated from a tendency to be dominated by either determinism or indeterminism. As knowledge about the real world accumulated, the cycles failed to repeat exactly, showing that there were advances in both camps. I cherry picked a few examples for Chapter 2 and even included a controversial sketch in the 1984 review version of TSW:
Progression of the determinism-indeterminism cycle as
represented by various Western philosophers.
Sophists, postmodernists, and other indeterminists hate this cartoon
ostensibly because it is simple, but mostly because its spiralic character
illustrates Hegel’s “negation of the negation.” This dictum, implying that
progress is inevitable, bedevils reactionaries and conservatives and gives hope
to progressives. It explains why you can’t go home again and why we will never
return to those five minutes in 1950 when all was perfect.
I have been asked to downplay the importance of Marx and dialectical
materialism. That is not possible. If you really believe that “there are material
causes for all effects,” then you must admit that you are not only a
determinist, but a materialist as well. You can see the appeal of any
philosophy that dares to use “materialism” in its name. Indeed, some Marxists
have considered dialectical materialism to be the scientific worldview. Aside
from the great religions, no other philosophy has had such a great effect on
the world and day-to-day life. This is true whether one was
promoting it or fighting against it. Previous philosophers have been
indeterminists in their own way even though one can always extract a few deterministic
ideas from their works. They became popular because they were useful to the
authorities who, above all, had to instill and enforce loyalty to survive. As
always, those who stepped over the line were ignored, confined, or executed.
The philosophical struggle came to a head with the publication of
Lenin’s “Materialism” in 1909 as a reaction to what he saw as the bourgeois sponsorship of idealism in physics. Subsequent events accelerated
the slander against materialism in the West. Materialism became covert among
scientists, who dared not mention its name. Most became too philosophically confused
or enfeebled to prevent the introduction of immaterialism into physics. The
dominance of religion provided an enormous reservoir of indeterministic ideas
that aided this regression.
Growing up in the fifties, we were taught to avoid reading or talking
about anything having to do with communism, materialism, Marx, Lenin, or
atheism—some of my earliest television memories are of Sen. McCarthy and HUAC,
which taught us lessons in persecution. The Vietnam War changed all that,
because we were being asked to put our lives on the line in opposition to the
ideas behind McCarthy’s words. Many of us tried to find out what we were fighting to overthrow. Eventually the words became less intimidating
than the prospect of an early, needless death.
Bill, you are correct that Marx and Engels gave little direction as to
how to proceed in science. I was struck, however, by Marx’s claim that it is not
consciousness that determines material conditions, but material conditions that
determine consciousness. This fit with my long-standing belief in determinism.
Of course, the relationship is really univironmental, as I eventually
discovered—the subjective and objective are in perpetual interaction. Sure,
Engels later formulated the three “laws” of dialectical materialism: 1) the
unity and conflict of opposites, 2) the transformation of quantity into
quality, and 3) the negation of the negation. These observations are sometimes
useful, but I could not see how disagreement with them would lead to the
objectification of motion, cosmogony, or religion. That is where Collingwood
and Bohm came in, as you will see in Chapter 3, which is
on "The Ten Assumptions of Science."]
2. You handle the matter/spirit dichotomy well, but I think
the better approach is to simply identify religious ideas as convenient methods
of dealing with the unknown and imposing social order. They were a refuge
for blind ignorance and de-facto authority, when knowledge and truth were
sparse.
[I partially agree, but this situation is still true for most of the
world. I do not find attacks on religion to be particularly helpful for getting
to the place I want to go: the philosophical elimination of free will as the
best expression of the proposition that “there are material causes for all
effects.”]
I'm not sure that it's valid to equate determinism
with the material view and indeterminism with the spiritual view. One can be a
determinist while still embracing acausality (true material randomness)
and one can be a spiritualist who believes in a predetermined plan of God
(dictating every natural and human event).
[You are partially correct, except that would not satisfy the
assumption that “there are material causes for all effects.” Aristotle and some
of the classical determinists incorrectly thought material randomness to be
acausal. This would mean that the microcosms involved were not subject to
Newton’s Second Law (F=ma). Calvin’s predestination eliminated free will too,
but substituted an immaterial actor in charge of carrying out the plan.]
3. I don't agree that determinism and free will are
contrary ideas. However, I see that you have a latter chapter discussing the
topic, so I'll reserve my comments.
[You write that you agree with the assumption that “there are material
causes for all effects” and that human abstractions are configurations of
synapses, but remark that “While the configurations themselves are
purely material, the content is not constrained by the laws of physics.” Univironmental
determinists consider all things and their motions as being constrained by the
laws of physics. I have no idea what you mean by “content” independent of the
universe—sounds like spiritualism to me.]
cotsw 001
cotsw 001
1 comment:
Wake up with determination. Have a good day :)
imarksweb.net
Post a Comment