David
de Hilster, President of Chappell Natural Philosophy Society, asks: “How did
you first get the idea the universe was infinite?”
That
is something most scientists seldom think about. I was no different. From 1962
to 1976 I mostly concentrated on laboratory experiments and field observations
in soil science, geology, and chemistry. I did have a propensity for
emphasizing logic[2]
and a distaste for contradiction.[3]
Always being curious, I tried to keep up with the latest developments in science.
I read American Laboratory and Industrial Research, free magazines in which
scientists sometimes were allowed to present articles outside the party line. One
particularly influential article even dared to contradict Einstein, suggesting space
was not perfectly empty.[4]
New Scientist was a big influence, getting me out of the box in which specialists
generally find themselves.[5]
Some of the articles inadvertently made me aware of the numerous contradictions
and paradoxes in physics and cosmogony.
Of
course, reading a few “broadening” articles was nice, but not enough. It seems
one does not switch beliefs overnight. I have to admit that as late as 1978[6]
I still was a Big Banger, although not a very good one. I remember drawing
little diagrams in which the stars at the end of the supposedly finite universe
gave off light into the “empty space” of the great beyond. I imagined “photons”
from two or more of these stars would crash together, somehow forming matter
once again. This was a desperate attempt to get away from the contradictions on
the other end of the Big Bang stick: the rumors of “heat death” and the
ultimate demise of the universe that were being promulgated at the time.
Philosophies
Change with Crisis
Little
did I know the key was to switch from finity to infinity. I
have been trying to pin down exactly when that happened. It turns out that
philosophies seldom change unless there is a crisis. In 1976, despite my
general affability, things were not going well at work. On July 4th I became so discouraged that I
faced off a guy who obviously wanted the campground and its swimming hole to
himself. He pointed a 32-special revolver at me saying he was the Zodiac killer
and planned to kill me and everyone in the campground. He asked a crucial question:
Do you believe me? The correct answer was “I don’t know.” Turns out he was only
kidding—so he said.
Traumatic events like that can
get your attention. Being well-trained academically, I tried to figure out my
discouragement by putting my thoughts together in a book. The first attempt was
entitled “Motivation: What it is and how to get it.” A second was “Power
Position and Power View.” A third was “The Chemical Meaning of Life.” This last
was a vast generalization on what I had learned as a lab rat. The basic
mechanism was “environmental determinism.” That was not original, but it did
fit my predilection to be on the deterministic side of free will arguments and
to acknowledge the importance of the environment. After all, “environmentalism”
had become all the rage after “Earth Day” in 1970. People were once again
showing signs of leaving their myopism behind.
Still, I had a vague feeling
something was missing. Wasn’t the thing itself just as important as its
environment? I remember sitting next to a tall pine tree at Showers Lake in the
Sierras thinking: How come that tree is not a mile high? Why does it stop
growing just in time to survive the 199-mph winds that would take it down?
Neo-Darwinism, of course, had an answer: Genes. Neo-Darwinism supposedly was the mechanism of evolution. But I was a
geoscientist; I wasn’t really satisfied with that. Everything around me was
evolving. With a little rainfall, the minerals in rocks formed under high
temperature and pressure were transformed into minerals stable at ambient
temperatures. Mountains turned into valleys and valleys turned into mountains.
The Sun, Moon, and the planets were evolving. There was more to evolution than
just genes and natural selection. Little did I know at the time that my search
for a more general mechanism for evolution would lead me down the path to infinity.
Discovery of the Universal Mechanism of Evolution
The search was futile. There
was no universal mechanism of evolution. Environmental determinism was not it
either. That was akin to the one-sided view proposed by Darwin as “natural
selection.” Mendel’s remedy—genetics—might work for the pine tree, but was
woefully lacking for the evolution of anything without genes. I needed a word
describing the combination that included the thing and its environment. I
discussed the problem at the dining room table with Elizabeth Patelke, a
long-time friend and a student of language. We came up with the solution:
“univironment.”[7] I
quickly and bravely anointed the result: “univironmental determinism,” as the universal mechanism of evolution. It
was so all-inclusive that it became the basis for the scientific worldview.[8]
With that focus, one begins to
think more about the insides and outsides of things and how those two portions
of the universe interact. We make mistakes when we overemphasize one or the
other. Systems philosophy, considered the “scientific world view” at the time,
tended to overemphasize the insides. That’s what the finite universe idea of
the Big Bang Theory was all about.
The univironmental idea does
not necessarily get you forthwith to infinity. As in Newtonian
mechanics, just because the insides and outsides of things produced results did
not mean that the insides and the outsides had to contain anything. After all,
Einstein had proclaimed that his light particle was “massless” (i.e., there was
nothing inside it) and cosmogonists implied the finite universe was expanding into
empty space (i.e., there was nothing outside it).
Nonetheless, I persisted. Everything
I had studied always had something inside it. And, now, everything always had
something outside it. In chemistry and geology every reaction and every rock
starts with something and ends up with something. A chemical equation displays
the univironmental interaction between what was and what will be. You cannot
change one side of the equation without the other side being changed. Early on,
I defined univironmental determinism as “what happens to a portion of the
universe is determined by the matter within and without”—no mention of
infinity.
While reading up on
determinism, I came across a comment that David Bohm had presented a strong
case for determinism. I read his “Causality and Chance in Modern Physics,”
which presented his “hidden variables theory” in opposition to the solipsistic
Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics. That was it for me. His logic
was impeccable. I had always been puzzled by the fact I always got plus or
minus errors no matter how much I tried to control an experiment.
Newton’s mechanics taught there were a finite number of causes for any effect.
Once you discovered them all, there would be no plus or minus. That never
happened. Bohm emphasized this infinite quality in direct opposition to the
Copenhageners, who attributed those variations to pure chance. That preserved
the finity assumption of Newtonian mechanics along with Einstein’s assumption
space was perfectly empty.
Publishing
My Books
Following
Bohm’s logic, I
assumed both micro (Aristotle) and macro (Newton) infinity in what was to be the
Eighth Assumption of Science (The universe is infinite, both in the microcosmic
and macrocosmic directions). That appeared first in the 1984 review manuscript
of "The Scientific Worldview."[9] It
was reiterated when “The Ten Assumptions of Science” was published in 2004. But
its full connection to univironmental determinism was not realized until 2007
when I wrote:
The Scientific Worldview describes how this
universe works via the universal mechanism of evolution, “univironmental
determinism.” Univironmental determinism is the simple proposition that what
happens to a portion of the universe is determined by the relationship between
the infinite matter in motion within (the microcosm) and the infinite matter in
motion without (the macrocosm).[10]
As you can see, there really
was no single Eureka moment for me—there were dozens of them. It took me almost
three decades to come up with the all-important statement quoted above. Along
the way, I had to discover: 1) the
universal mechanism of evolution, 2) the
scientific worldview, 3) the Ten Assumptions of Science, 4) neomechanics, which
modifies classical mechanics by including infinity, and finally
5) Infinite Universe Theory, which ultimately will replace the Big Bang Theory
in a process sure to become the Last Cosmological Revolution. Why so sure about
this? Once you fully understand Infinite Universe Theory and its ramifications,
the switch from the assumption of finity to the assumption of infinity
is irreversible.
[1]Also published in the new online science magazine “ScienceWoke” [http://sciencewoke.org/finding-infinity/].
[2] Borchardt, Glenn, 1975, Dithionite-citrate-bicarbonate procedure
(DCB) for iron removal: Soil Science Society of America Proceedings, v. 39, p.
807.
[3] Borchardt, Glenn, 1978, Catastrophe theory: Application to the
Permian mass extinction: Comments and reply: COMMENT: Geology, v. 6, no. 8, p.
453. [DOI: 10.1130/0091-7613(1978)6<453a:ctattp>2.0.CO;2453a:ctattp>].
[4] Dudley, H.C., 1977, The neutrino sea--hypothesis or reality?:
Industrial Research, p. 51-54.
[5] Clube, Victor, 1978, Do we need a revolution in astronomy?: New
Scientist, v. 80, p. 284-286; Davies, Paul, 1978, Chance or choice: Is the Universe
an accident?: New Scientist, v. 80, p. 506-508; Steen, L.A., 1978, A new
perspective on infinity: New Scientist, v. 80, p. 448-451.
[6] On 19771217 my notes had a proposed chapter entitled “Universe,
origin of.”
[7] By 19780529, an early draft had the word “univironment.”
[8] Borchardt, Glenn, 2007, The Scientific Worldview: Beyond Newton and
Einstein: Lincoln, NE, iUniverse, 411 p. [http://www.scientificphilosophy.com/].
[9] Borchardt, Glenn, 1984, The scientific worldview: Berkeley,
California, Progressive Science Institute, 343 p. [DOI: 10.13140/RG.2.2.16123.52006].
[10] Borchardt, Glenn, 2007, The scientific worldview and the demise of
cosmogony, in Whitney, C.K., Proceedings of the Natural Philosophy Alliance:
University of Connecticut, Storrs, CN, Natural Philosophy Alliance, v. 4, no.
1, p. 16-19 [http://scientificphilosophy.com/Downloads/TSWATDOC.pdf].
1 comment:
I would think Hilster would know this, but I do not know him.
Conceptualize what "nothing" is or isn't.
IF there is no such thing one is left with something. and this something has to be infinite because there is no such thing as nothing. From my book. Forthcoming when?
G
Post a Comment